Politics Aristotle

The Politics, by the ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle, is one of the most influential texts in political philosophy. In it, Aristotle explores the role that the political community should play in developing the virtue of its citizens. One of his central ideas is that "Man is a political animal," meaning that people can only become virtuous by active participation in the political community. Aristotle also criticizes his teacher Plato, classifies and evaluates six different types of constitutions and political institutions, and describes his vision of the ideal state. Aristotle's views on women and slavery are unenlightened by today's standards, but his work remains enduring and relevant to this day.

ARISTOTLE (384 BC - 322 BC), translated by Benjamin JOWETT (1817 - 1893)


01 - Book One, Sections I-V


02 - Book One, Sections VI-IX


03 - Book One, Sections X-XIII


04 - Book Two, Sections I-IV


05 - Book Two, Sections V-VI


06 - Book Two, Sections VII-VIII


07 - Book Two, Sections IX-X


08 - Book Two, Sections XI-XII


09 - Book Three, Sections I-IV


10 - Book Three, Sections V-IX


11 - Book Three, Sections X-XIII


12 - Book Three, Sections XIV-XVIII


13 - Book Four, Sections I-IV


14 - Book Four, Sections V-X


15 - Book Four, Sections XI-XIII


16 - Book Four, Sections XIV-XVI


17 - Book Five, Sections I-IV


18 - Book Five, Sections V-VII


19 - Book Five, Sections VIII-IX


20 - Book Five, Section X


21 - Book Five, Sections XI-XII


22 - Book Six, Sections I-IV


23 - Book Six, Sections V-VIII


24 - Book Seven, Sections I-III


25 - Book Seven, Sections IV-IX


26 - Book Seven, Sections X-XII


27 - Book Seven, Sections XIII-XIV


28 - Book Seven, Sections XV-XVII


29 - Book Eight, Sections I-IV


30 - Book Eight, Sections V-VII


Book I.
In the first book, Aristotle discusses the city (polis) or "political community" (koinōnia politikē) as opposed to other types of communities and partnerships such as the household (oikos) and village. The highest form of community is the polis. Aristotle comes to this conclusion because he believes the public life is far more virtuous than the private and because men are "political animals". He begins with the relationship between the city and man (I. 1–2), and then specifically discusses the household (oikos) (I. 3–13). He takes issue with the view that political rule, kingly rule, rule over slaves and rule over a household or village are only different in size. He then examines in what way the city may be said to be natural.

Aristotle discusses the parts of the household (oikos), which includes slaves, leading to a discussion of whether slavery can ever be just and better for the person enslaved or is always unjust and bad. He distinguishes between those who are slaves because the law says they are and those who are slaves by nature, saying the inquiry hinges on whether there are any such natural slaves. Only someone as different from other people as the body is from the soul or beasts are from human beings would be a slave by nature, Aristotle concludes, all others being slaves solely by law or convention. Some scholars have therefore concluded that the qualifications for natural slavery preclude the existence of such a being.

Aristotle then moves to the question of property in general, arguing that the acquisition of property does not form a part of household management (oikonomike) and criticizing those who take it too seriously. It is necessary, but that does not make it a part of household management any more than it makes medicine a part of household management just because health is necessary. He criticizes income based upon trade and upon interest, saying that those who become avaricious do so because they forget that money merely symbolizes wealth without being wealth and "contrary to nature" on interest because it increases by itself not through exchange.

Book I concludes with Aristotle's assertion that the proper object of household rule is the virtuous character of one's wife and children, not the management of slaves or the acquisition of property. Rule over the slaves is despotic, rule over children kingly, and rule over one's wife political (except there is no rotation in office). Aristotle questions whether it is sensible to speak of the "virtue" of a slave and whether the "virtues" of a wife and children are the same as those of a man before saying that because the city must be concerned that its women and children be virtuous, the virtues that the father should instill are dependent upon the regime and so the discussion must turn to what has been said about the best regime.

Book II.
Book II examines various views concerning the best regime. It opens with an analysis of the regime presented in Plato's Republic (2. 1–5) before moving to that presented in Plato's Laws (2. 6). Aristotle then discusses the systems presented by two other philosophers, Phaleas of Chalcedon (2. 7) and Hippodamus of Miletus (2. 8).

After addressing regimes invented by theorists, Aristotle moves to the examination of three regimes that are commonly held to be well managed. These are the Spartan (2. 9), Cretan (2. 10), and Carthaginian (2. 11). The book concludes with some observations on regimes and legislators.

Book III.
Who can be a citizen?
"He who has the power to take part in the deliberative or judicial administration of any state is said by us to be a citizen of that state; and speaking generally, a state is a body of citizens sufficing for the purpose of life. But in practice a citizen is defined to be one of whom both the parents are citizens; others insist on going further back; say two or three or more grandparents." Aristotle asserts that a citizen is anyone who can take part in the governmental process. He finds that most people in the polis are capable of being citizens. This is contrary to the Platonist view which asserts that only very few can take part in the deliberative or judicial administration of the state.

Classification of constitution.
Just distribution of political power.
Types of monarchies:
Monarchy: exercised over voluntary subjects, but limited to certain functions; the king was a general and a judge, and had control of religion.
Absolute: government of one for the absolute good
Barbarian: legal and hereditary + willing subjects
Dictator: installed by foreign power elective dictatorship + willing subjects (elective tyranny)

Book IV.
Tasks of political theory
Why are there many types of constitutions?
Types of democracies
Types of oligarchies
Polity (Constitutional Government) – highest form of government
When perverted, a Polity becomes a Democracy, the least harmful derivative government as regarded by Aristotle.
Government offices

Book V.
Constitutional change
Revolutions in different types of constitutions and ways to preserve constitutions
Instability of tyrannies

Book VI.
Democratic constitutions
Oligarchic constitutions

Book VII.
Best state and best life
Ideal state. Its population, territory, position etc.
Citizens of the ideal state
Marriage and children

Book VIII.
Education in the ideal state

Comments

Random Post